VAISHESIKA
Vaisheshika, or Vaiśeṣika, (Sanskrit:वैशॆषिक) is
one of the six Hindu schools of philosophy (orthodox Vedic systems) of India.
Historically, it has been closely associated with the Hindu school of logic,
Nyaya.
Vaisesika espouses a form of atomism and postulates that all
objects in the physical universe are reducible to a finite number of atoms.
Originally proposed by the sage Kaṇāda (or Kana-bhuk, literally,
atom-eater) around the 2nd century BC.
Overview
Although the Vaishesika system developed independently from
the Nyaya, the two eventually merged because of their closely related
metaphysical theories. In its classical form, however, the Vaishesika school
differed from the Nyaya in one crucial respect: where Nyaya accepted four
sources of valid knowledge, the Vaishesika accepted only perception and
inference. Although not among Kanada's original philosophies, later Vaishesika
atomism also differs from the atomic theory of modern science by claiming the
functioning of atoms(or their characterization because of which they function
in their way) was guided or directed by the will of the Supreme Being. This is
therefore a theistic form of atomism.
An alternative view would qualify the above in that the
holism evident in the ancient texts mandate the identification of six separate
traditional environments of philosophy, consisting of three sets of two
pairs.
Literature of Vaisheshika
The earliest systematic exposition of the Vaisheshika is
found in the Vaiśeṣika
Sūtra of Kaṇāda
(or Kaṇabhaksha). This treatise is divided
into ten books. The two commentaries on the Vaiśeṣika Sūtra, Rāvaṇabhāṣya and Bhāradvājavṛtti are no more extant. Praśastapāda’s
Padārthadharmasaṁgraha
(c. 4th century) is the next important work of this school. Though commonly
known as bhāṣya
of Vaiśeṣika Sūtra, this treatise is basically
an independent work on the subject. The next Vaisheshika treatise, Candra’s
Daśapadārthaśāstra (648) based on Praśastapāda’s treatise is available only in
Chinese translation. The earliest available on Praśastapāda’s treatise is
Vyomaśiva’s Vyomavatī (8th century). The other three commentaries are
Śridhara’s Nyāyakandalī (991), Udayana’s Kiranāvali (10th century) and
Śrivatsa’s Līlāvatī (11th century). Śivāditya’s Saptapadārthī which also
belongs to the same period, presents the Nyāya and the Vaiśeṣika principles as a part of one whole.
Śaṁkarā Miśra’s Upaskāra on Vaiśeṣika Sūtra is also an important work.
The categories or padartha
According to the Vaisheshika school, all things which exist,
which can be cognised, and which can be named are padārthas (literal meaning:
the meaning of a word), the objects of experience. All objects of experience
can be classified into six categories, dravya (substance), guṇa (quality), karma (activity), sāmānya
(generality), viśeṣa
(particularity) and samavāya (inherence). Later Vaiśeṣikas (Śrīdhara and Udayana and
Śivāditya) added one more category abhāva (non-existence). The first three
categories are defined as artha (which can perceived) and they have real
objective existence. The last three categories are defined as budhyapekṣam (product of intellectual
discrimination) and they are logical categories.
1. Dravya (substance): The substances are
conceived as 9 in number. They are, pṛthvī (earth), ap (water), tejas (fire),
vāyu (air), ākaśa (sky), kāla (time), dik (space), ātman (self) and manas
(mind). The first five are called bhūtas, the substances having some specific
qualities so that they could be perceived by one or the other external senses.
2. Guṇa (quality):
The Vaiśeṣika Sūtra mentions 17 guṇas
(qualities), to which Praśastapāda added another 7. While a substance is
capable of existing independently by itself, a guṇa(quality)
cannot exist so. The original 17 guṇas (qualities) are, rūpa (colour), rasa
(taste), gandha (smell), sparśa (touch), saṁkhyā (number), parimāṇa
(size/dimension/quantity), pṛthaktva (inidividuality), saṁyoga
(conjunction/accompaniments), vibhāga (disjunction), paratva (priority),
aparatva (posteriority), buddhi (knowledge), sukha (pleasure), duḥkha
(pain), icchā (desire), dveṣa (aversion) and prayatna (effort). To
these Praśastapāda added gurutva (heaviness), dravatva (fluidity), sneha
(viscosity), dharma (merit), adharma (demerit), śabda (sound) and saṁkāsra
(faculty).
3. Karma (activity): The karmas (activities)
like guṇas (qualities) have no separate
existence, they belong to the substances. But while a quality is a permanent
feature of a substance, an activity is a transient one. Ākaśa (sky), kāla
(time), dik (space) and ātman (self), though substances, are devoid of karma
(activity).
4. Sāmānya (generality): Since there are
plurality of substances, there will be relations among them. When a property is
found common to many substances, it is called sāmānya.
5. Viśeṣa (particularity):
By means of viśeṣa
, we are able to perceive substances as different from one another. As the
ultimate atoms are innumerable so are the viśeṣas.
6. Samavāya (inherence): Kaṇāda
defined samavāya as the relation between the cause and the effect. Praśastapāda
defined it as the relationship existing between the substances that are
inseparable, standing to one another in the relation of the container and the
contained. The relation of samavāya is not perceivable but only inferable from
the inseparable connection of the substances.
Epistemology and syllogism
The early vaiśeṣika epistemology considered only
pratyaksha (perception) and anumāna (inference) as the pramaṇas (means of valid knowledge). The
other two means of valid knowledge accepted by the Nyaya school, upamāna
(comparison) and śabda (verbal testimony) were considered as included in
anumāna. The syllogism of the vaiśeṣika school was similar to that of the Nyaya,
but the names given by Praśastapāda to the 5 members of syllogism are
different.
The atomic theory
The early vaiśeṣika texts presented the following
syllogism to prove that all objects i.e. the four bhūtas, pṛthvī (earth), ap (water), tejas (fire)
and vāyu (air) are made of indivisible paramāṇus (atoms): Assume that the matter is
not made of indivisible atoms, and that it is continuous. Take a stone. One can
divide this up into infinitely many pieces (since matter is continuous). Now,
the Himalayan mountain range also has infinitely many pieces, so one may build
another Himalayan mountain range with the infinite number of pieces that one
has. One begins with a stone and ends up with the Himalayas, which is obviously
ridiculous - so the original assumption that matter is continuous must be
wrong, and so all objects must be made up of a finite number of paramāṇus (atoms).
According to the vaiśeṣika school, the trasareṇu (dust particles visible in the
sunbeam coming through a small window hole) are the smallest mahat
(perceivable) particles and defined as tryaṇukas (triads). These are made of three
parts, each of which are defined as dvyaṇuka (dyad). The dvyaṇukas are conceived as made of two
parts, each of which are defined as paramāṇu (atom). The paramāṇus (atoms) are indivisible and eternal,
they can neither be created nor destroyed. Each paramāṇu (atom) possesses its own distinct
viśeṣa (individuality).
Later developments
Over the centuries, the school merged with the Nyaya school
of Indian philosophy to form the combined school of nyāya-vaiśeṣika. The school suffered a natural
decline in India after the 15th century.
NYAYA
Nyāya
(Sanskrit ni-āyá, literally "recursion", used in the sense of
"syllogism, inference") is the name given to one of the six orthodox
or astika schools of Hindu philosophy—specifically the school of logic. The
Nyaya school of philosophical speculation is based on texts known as the Nyaya
Sutras, which were written by Aksapada Gautama from around the 2nd century CE.
Overview
The
most important contribution made by the Nyaya school to modern Hindu thought is
its methodology. This methodology is based on a system of logic that,
subsequently, has been adopted by the majority of the other Indian schools,
orthodox or not. This is comparable to how Western science and philosophy can
be said to be largely based on Aristotelian logic.
However,
Nyaya differs from Aristotelian logic in that it is more than logic in its own
right. Its followers believed that obtaining valid knowledge was the only way
to obtain release from suffering. They therefore took great pains to identify
valid sources of knowledge and to distinguish these from mere false opinions.
Nyaya is thus a form of epistemology in addition to logic.
According
to the Nyaya school, there are exactly four sources of knowledge (pramanas):
perception, inference, comparison, and testimony. Knowledge obtained through
each of these can, of course, still be either valid or invalid. As a result,
Nyaya scholars again went to great pains to identify, in each case, what it
took to make knowledge valid, in the process creating a number of explanatory
schemes. In this sense, Nyaya is probably the closest Indian equivalent to
contemporary analytic philosophy.
Sixteen
padarthas or categories
The
Nyaya metaphysics recognizes sixteen padarthas or categories and includes all
six (or seven) categories of the Vaisheshika in the second one of them, called
prameya. These sixteen categories are pramāṇa (valid means of knowledge), prameya
(objects of valid knowledge), saṁśaya (doubt), prayojana (aim), dṛṣṭānta
(example), siddhānta (conclusion), avayava (members of syllogism), tarka
(hypothetical reasoning), nirṇaya (settlement), vāda (discussion),
jalpa (wrangling), vitaṇḍā (cavilling), hetvābhāsa (fallacy),
chala (quibbling), jāti (sophisticated refutation) and nigrahasthāna (point of
defeat).
Epistemology
The
Nyaya epistemology considers knowledge (jñāna) or cognition (buddhi) as
apprehension (upalabdhi) or consciousness (anubhava). Knowledge may be valid or
invalid. The Naiyayikas (the Nyaya scholars) accepted four valid means (pramaṇa)
of obtaining valid knowledge (prama) - perception (pratyakṣa),
inference (anumāna), comparison (upamāna) and verbal testimony (śabda). Invalid
knowledge includes memory (smṛti), doubt (saṁśaya),
error (viparyaya) and hypothetical reasoning (tarka).
Perception
Pratyakṣa
(perception) occupies the foremost position in the Nyaya epistemology.
Perception is defined by Akṣapāda Gautama in his Nyaya Sutra
(I,i.4) as a 'non-erroneous cognition which is produced by the intercourse of
sense-organs with the objects, which is not associated with a name and
well-defined'. Perception can be of two types, laukika (ordinary) and alaukika
(extraordinary).
Ordinary
perception
Ordinary
(Laukika or Sadharana) perception is of six types - visual-by eyes,
olfactory-by nose, auditory-by ears, tactile-by skin, gustatory-by tongue and
mental-by mind.
Extra-ordinary
perception
Extraordinary
(Alaukika or Asadharana) perception is of three types, viz., Samanyalakshana
(perceiving generality from a particular object), Jñanalakshana (when one sense
organ can also perceive qualities not attributable to it, as when seeing a
chili, one knows that it would be bitter or hot), and Yogaja (when certain
human beings, from the power of Yoga, can perceive past, present and future and
have supernatural abilities, either complete or some).
Determinate and indeterminate perception
The
Naiyayika maintains two modes or stages in perception. The first is called
nirvikalpa (indeterminate), when one just perceives an object without being
able to know its features, and the second savikalpa (determinate), when one is
able to clearly know an object. All laukika and alaukika pratyakshas are
savikalpa, but it is necessarily preceded by an earlier stage when it is
indeterminate. Vātsāyana says that if an object is perceived with its name we
have determinate perception but if it is perceived without a name, we have
indeterminate perception. Jayanta Bhatta says that indeterminate perception
apprehends substance, qualities and actions and universals as separate and
indistinct something and also it does not have any association with name, while
determinate perception aprrehends all these together with a name. There is yet
another stage called Pratyabhijñā, when one is able to re-recognise something
on the basis of memory.
Inference
Anumāna (inference) is one of the most
important contributions of the Nyaya. It can be of two types: inference for
oneself (Svarthanumana, where one does not need any formal procedure, and at
the most the last three of their 5 steps), and inference for others
(Parathanumana, which requires a systematic methodology of 5 steps). Inference
can also be classified into 3 types: Purvavat (inferring an unperceived effect
from a perceived cause), Sheshavat (inferring an unperceived cause from a
perceived effect) and Samanyatodrishta (when inference is not based on
causation but on uniformity of co-existence). A detailed anaysis of error is
also given, explaining when anumana could be false.
Comparison
Upamāna,
which can be roughly translated as comparison is the knowledge of the
relationship between a word and the object denoted by the word. It is produced
by the knowledge of resemblance or similarity, given some pre-description of
the new object beforehand.
Verbal testimony
Śabda
or verbal testimony is defined as the statement of a trustworthy person
(āptavākya), and consists in understanding its meaning. It can be of two types,
Vaidika (Vedic), which are the words of the four sacred Vedas, and are
described as the Word of God, having been composed by God, and Laukika, or
words and writings of trustworthy human beings. while Vaidika testimony is
perfect because the Vedas are spoken by God, Laukika testimony are is not
infallible.
Theory of inference
The
methodology of inference involves a combination of induction and deduction by
moving from particular to particular via generality. It has five steps, as in
the example shown:
*
There is fire on the hill (called Pratijñā, required to be proved)
*
Because there is smoke there (called Hetu, reason)
*
Wherever there is smoke, there is fire, e.g. in a kitchen (called Udāhārana,
example of vyāpti)
*
The hill has smoke that is pervaded by fire (called Upanaya, reaffirmation or
application)
*
Therefore there is fire on the hill (called Nigamana, conclusion)
In
Nyāya terminology for this example, the hill would be called as paksha (minor
term), the fire is called as sādhya (major term), the smoke is called as hetu,
and the relationship between the smoke and the fire is called as vyāpti(middle
term). Hetu further has five characteristics:
(1)
It must be present in the Paksha,
(2)
It must be present in all positive instances,
(3)
It must be absent in all negative instances,
(4)
It must not incompatible with the minor term or Paksha and
(5)
All other contradictions by other means of knowledge should be absent.
The
fallacies in Anumana (hetvābhasa) may occur due to the following:
1.
Asiddha: It is the unproved hetu that results in this fallacy. [Paksadharmata]
*
Ashrayasiddha: If Paksha [minor term] itself is unreal, then there cannot be
locus of the hetu. e.g. The sky-lotus is fragrant, because it is a lotus like
any other lotus.
*
Svarupasiddha: Hetu cannot exist in paksa at all. E.g. Sound is a quality,
because it is visible.
*
Vyapyatvasiddha: Conditional hetu. `Wherever there is fire, there is smoke'.
The presence of smoke is due to wet fuel.
2.
Savyabhichara: This is the fallacy of irregular hetu.
*
Sadharana: The hetu is too wide. It is present in both sapaksa and vipaksa.
`The hill has fire because it is knowable'.
*
Asadharana: The hetu is too narrow. It is only present in the Paksha, it is not
present in the Sapaksa and in the Vipaksha. `Sound is eternal because it is
audible'.
*
Anupasamhari: Here the hetu is non-exclusive. The hetu is all-inclusive and
leaves nothing by way of sapaksha or vipaksha. e.g. 'All things are non-ternal,
because they are knowable'.
3.
Satpratipaksa: Here the hetu is contradicted by another hetu. If both have
equal force, then nothing follows. 'Sound is eternal, because it is audible',
and 'Sound is non-eternal, because it is produced'. Here 'audible' is
counter-balanced by 'produced' and both are of equal force.
4.
Badhita: When another proof (as by perception) definitely contradicts and
disproves the middle term (hetu). 'Fire is cold because it is a substance'.
5.
Viruddha: Instead of proving something it is proving the opposite. 'Sound is
eternal because it is produced'.
The Nyaya theory of causation
A
cause is defined as an unconditional and invariable antecedent of an effect and
an effect as an unconditional and invariable consequent of a cause. The same
cause produces the same effect; and the same effect is produced by the same
cause. The cause is not present in any hidden form whatsoever in its effect.
The
following conditions should be met:
1.
The cause must be antencedent [Purvavrtti]
2.
Invariability [Niyatapurvavrtti]
3.
Unconditionality [Ananyathasiddha]
Nyaya
recognizes five kinds of accidental antecedents [Anyathasiddha]
1.
Mere accidental antecedent. E.g., The colour of the potter's cloth.
2.
Remote cause is not a cause because it is not unconditional. E.g., The father
of the potter.
3.
The co-effects of a cause are not causally related.
4.
Eternal substances, or eternal conditions are not unconditional antecedents.
e.g. space.
5.
Unnecessary things, e.g. the donkey of the potter.
Nyaya
recognizes three kinds of cause:
1.
Samavayi, material cause. E.g. Thread of a cloth.
2.
Asamavayi, colour of the thread which gives the colour of the cloth.
3.
Nimitta', efficient cause, e.g. the weaver of the cloth.
Anyathakyativada of Nyaya
The
Nyaya theory of error is similar to that of Kumarila's Viparita-khyati (see Mimamsa).
The Naiyayikas also believe like Kumarila that error is due to a wrong
synthesis of the presented and the represented objects. The represented object
is confused with the presented one. The word 'anyatha' means 'elsewise' and
'elsewhere' and both these meanings are brought out in error. The presented
object is perceived elsewise and the represented object exists elsewhere. They
further maintain that knowledge is not intrinsically valid but becomes so on
account of extraneous conditions (paratah pramana during both validity and
invalidity).
Nyaya argument for the existence of God
Early
Naiyayikas wrote very little about God, i.e., Ishvara (literally, the Supreme
Lord). However, later Buddhists in India had become from agnostic to strictly
atheistic. As a reaction, the later Naiyayikas entered into disputes with the
Buddhists and tried to prove the existence of God through logic. They made this
question a challenge to their own existence. They gave the following nine
proofs for the existence of God, enlisted in Udayana's Nyaya Kusumanjali:
* Kāryāt (lit. "from effect"): An effect is produced by a cause,
and similarly, the universe must also have a cause. Causes (according to
Naiyayikas) are of three kinds: Samavayi (in case of the universe, the atoms),
Asamavayi (the association of atoms) and Nimitta (which is Ishvara). The active
cause of the world must have an absolute knowledge of all the material of
creation, and hence it must be God. Hence from the creation, the existence of
the Creator is proved.
* Āyojanāt (lit., from combination): Atoms are inactive and properties
are unphysical. So it must be God who creates the world with his will by
causing the atoms to join. Self-combination of inanimate and lifeless things is
not possible, otherwise atoms would only combine at random, creating chaos.
There is to be seen the hand of a wise organizer behind the systematic grouping
of the ultimate atoms into dyads and molecules. That final organizer is God.
* Dhŗité (lit., from support): Just as a material thing falls
off without a support, similarly, God is the supporter and bearer of this
world, without which the world would not have remained integrated. This
universe is hence superintended within God, which proves his existence.
* Padāt (lit., from word): Every word has the capability to
represent a certain object. It is the will of God that a thing should be
represented by a certain word. Similarly, no knowledge can come to us of the
different things here unless there is a source of this knowledge. The origin of
all knowledge should be omniscient and, consequently, omnipotent. Such a being
is not to be seen in this universe, and so it must be outside it. This being is
God.
* Pratyatah (lit, from faith): the Hindu holy scriptures, the
Vedas, are regarded as the source of eternal knowledge. Their knowledge is free
from fallacies and are widely believed as a source of proof. Their authors
cannot be human beings because human knowledge is limited. They cannot obtain
knowledge of past, present, and future, and in depth knowledge of mind. Hence,
only God can be the creator of the Vedas. Hence, his existence is proved from
his being the author of the Vedas, which he revealed to various sages over a
period of time.
* Shrutéh (lit., from scriptures): The Shrutis, e.g., the Vedas
extol God and talk about his existence. "He is the lord of all subjects,
omniscient, and knower of one's internal feelings; He is the creator, cause and
destroyer of the world", say the Shrutis. The Shrutis are regarded as a
source of proofs by Naiyanikas. Hence, the existence of God is proved.
* Vākyāt (lit., from precepts): Again, the Veda must have been
produced by a person because it has the nature of "sentences," i.e.,
the sentences of the Veda were produced by a person because they have the
nature of sentences, just as the sentences of beings like ourselves. That
person must have been God.
* Samkhyāvişheshāt (lit., from the
specialty of numbers): The
size of a dyad or a molecule depends on the number of the atoms that constitute
it. This requisite number of the atoms that form a particular compound could
not have been originally the object of the perception of any human being; so
its contemplator must be God.
* Adŗişhţāt (lit., from the unforeseen): It is seen that some people in
this world are happy, some are in misery. Some are rich, and some are poor. The
Naiyanikas explain this by the concept of Karma and reincarnation. The fruit of
an individual's actions does not always lie within the reach of the individual
who is the agent. There ought to be, therefore, a dispenser of the fruits of
actions, and this supreme dispenser is God.
Nyaya arguments for monotheism
Not
only have the Naiyanikas given proofs for the existence of God, but they have
also given an argument that such a God can only be one. In the Nyaya
Kusumanjali, this is discussed against the proposition of the Mimamsa
school—that let us assume there were many demigods (Devas) and sages (rishis)
in the beginning, who wrote the Vedas and created the world. Nyaya says that:
[if
they assume such] omniscient beings, those endowed with the various superhuman
faculties of assuming infinitesimal size, and so on, and capable of creating
everything, then we reply that the law of parsimony bids us assume only one
such, namely Him, the adorable Lord. There can be no confidence in a
non-eternal and non omniscient being, and hence it follows that according to
the system which rejects God, the tradition of the Veda is simultaneously
overthrown; there is no other way open.
In
other words, Nyaya says that the polytheist would have to give elaborate proofs
for the existence and origin of his several celestial spirits, none of which
would be logical. So it is much more logical to assume only One, eternal and
omniscient God.
Literature of Nyaya
The
earliest text of the Nyaya School is the Nyāya Sūtra of Akṣapāda
Gautama. The text is divided into five books, each having two sections.
Vātsāyana’s Nyāya Bhāṣya is a classic commentary on the Nyāya
Sūtra. Udyotakara’s Nyāya Vārttika (6th century CE) is written to defend
Vātsāyana against the attacks made by Dignāga. Vācaspati Miśra’s
Nyāyavārttikatātparyaṭīkā (9th century CE) is the next major
exposition of this school. Two other texts, Nyāyaṣūcinibandha
and Nyāyasūtraddhāra are also attributed to him. Udayana’s (984 CE)
Nyāyatātparyapariśuddhi is an important commentary on Vācaspati’s treatise. His
Nyāyakusumāñjali is the first systematic account of theistic Nyāya. His other
works include Ātmatattvaviveka, Kiraṇāvali and Nyāyapariśiṣṭa.
Jayanta Bhatta’s Nyāyamañjari (10th century CE) is basically an independent
work. Bhāsavarajña’s Nyāyasāra (10th century CE) is a survey of Nyāya
philosophy).
The
later works on Nyāya accepted the Vaiśeṣika categories and Varadarāja’s
Tārkikarakṣā (12th century CE) is a notable treatise
of this syncretist school. Keśava Miśra’s Tārkabhaṣā
(13th century CE) is another important work of this school.
Gangeśa
Upādhyāya’s Tattvacintāmaṇi (12th century CE) is the first major
treatise of the new school of Navya Nyāya. His son, Vardhamāna Upādhyāya’s
Nyāyanibandhaprakāśa (1225 CE), though a commentary on Udayana’s
Nyāyatātparyapariśuddhi, incorporated his father’s views. Jayadeva wrote a
commentary on Tattvacintāmaṇi known as Āloka (13th century CE).
Vāsudeva Sārvabhauma’s Tattvacintāmaṇivyākhyā (16th century CE) is first
great work of Navadvipa school of Navya Nyāya. Raghunātha Śiromaṇi’s
Tattvacintāmaṇidīdhiti and Padārthakhaṇḍana
are the next important works of this school. Viśvanatha’s Nyāyasūtravṛtti
(17th century CE) is also a notable work[7]. The Commentaries on Tattvacintāmaṇidīdhiti
by Jagadish Tarkalankar (17th century CE) and Gadadhar Bhattacharya (17th
century CE) are the last two notable works of this school.
Ānnaṁbhatta
(17th century CE) tried to develop a consistent system by combining the ancient
and the new schools, Prācina nyāya and Navya nyāya and Vaiśeṣika
to develop the nyāya-vaiśeṣika school. His Tarkasaṁgraha
and Dīpikā are the popular manuals of this school.
MIMAMSA
Mīmāmsā
(मीमांसा), a Sanskrit word meaning
"investigation", is the name of an astika ("orthodox")
school of Hindu philosophy whose primary enquiry is into the nature of dharma
based on close hermeneutics of the Vedas. Its core tenets are ritualism
(orthopraxy), anti-asceticism and anti-mysticism. The central aim of the school
is elucidation of the nature of dharma, understood as a set ritual obligations
and prerogatives to be performed properly. The nature of dharma isn't
accessible to reason or observation, and must be inferred from the authority of
the revelation contained in the Vedas, which are considered eternal, authorless
(apaurusheyatva), and infallible.
Mimamsa
strongly concerned with textual exegesis, and consequently gave rise to the
study of philology and the philosophy of language. Its notion of shabda
"speech" as indivisible unity of sound and meaning (signifier and
signified) is due to Bhartrhari (7th century).
Terminology
Mimamsa
is also known as Pūrva Mīmāṃsā ("prior" inquiry, also
Karma-Mīmāṃsā), in contrast to Uttara Mīmāṃsā
("posterior" inquiry, also Brahma-Mīmāṃsā)
is the opposing school of Vedanta. This division is based on the notion of a
dichotomy of the Vedic texts into a karma-kāṇḍa, the department of the Veda treating
of sacrificial rites (Samhitas and Brahmanas), and the jñāna-kāṇḍa
dealing with the knowledge of Brahman (the Upanishads).
History
The
school's origins lie in the scholarly traditions of the final centuries BCE,
when the priestly ritualism of Vedic sacrifice was being marginalized by Buddhism
and Vedanta. To counteract this challenge, several groups emerged dedicated to
demonstrating the validity of the Vedic texts by rigid formulation of rules for
their interpretation. The school gathers momentum in the Gupta period with
Śābara, and reaches its apex in the 7th to 8th centuries with Kumārila Bha..a
and Prabhākara.
The
school for some time in the Early Middle Ages exerted near-dominant influence
on learned Hindu thought, and is credited as a major force contributing to the
decline of Buddhism in India, but it has fallen into decline in the High Middle
Ages and today is all but eclipsed by Vedanta.
Mimamsa texts
The
foundational text for the Mimamsa school is the Purva Mimamsa Sutras of Jaimini
(ca. 3rd to 1st century BCE). A major commentary was composed by Śābara in ca.
the 5th or 6th century CE. The school reaches its height with Kumārila Bhaṭṭa
and Prabhākara (fl. ca. 700 CE). Both Kumarila Bhatta and Prabhākara (along
with Murāri, whose work is no more extant) have written extensive commentaries
on Śābara's Mimamsasutrabhāshyam. Kumārila Bhatta, Mandana Misra, Parthasarathi
Misra, Sucharita Misra, Ramakrishna Bhatta, Madhava Subhodini, Sankara Bhatta,
Krsnayajvan, Anantadeva, Gaga Bhatta, Ragavendra Tirtha, VijayIndhra Tirtha,
Appayya Dikshitar, Paruthiyur Krishna Sastri, Mahomahapadyaya Sri Ramsubba
Sastri, Sri Venkatsubba Sastri, Sri A. Chinnaswami Sastri, Sengalipuram
Vaidhyanatha Dikshitar were some of the Mimamsa Scholars.
The
Mīmāṁsā
Sūtra of Jaimini (c. 3rd century BCE) has summed up the general rules of nyāya
for Vedic interpretation. The text has 12 chapters, of which the first chapter
is of philosophical value. The commentaries on the Mīmāṁsā
Sūtra by Bhartṛmitra, Bhavadāsa, Hari and Upavarṣa
are no more extant. Śabara (c. 1st century BCE) is the first commentator of the
Mīmāṁsā
Sūtra, whose work is available to us. His bhāṣya
is the basis of all later works of Mīmāṁsā . Kumārila Bhaṭṭa
(7th century CE), the founder of the first school of the Mīmāṁsā
commented on both the Sūtra and its Śabara Bhāṣya.
His treatise consists of 3 parts, the Ślokavārttika, the Tantravārttika and
the Ṭupṭīkā. Manḍana
Miśra (8th century CE) was a follower of Kumārila, who wrote Vidhiviveka and
Mīmāṁsānukramaṇī.
There are several commentaries on the works of Kumārila. Sucarita Miśra wrote a
Kāśikā (commentary) on the Ślokavārttika. Someśvara Bhatta wrote Nyāyasudhā,
also known as Rāṇaka, a commentary on the
Tantravārttika. Pārthasarathi Miśra wrote Nyāyaratnākara (1300 CE), another
commentary on the Ślokavārttika. He also wrote Śāstradīpikā, an independent
work on the Mīmāṁsā and Tantraratna. Venkaṭa
Dīkṣita’s
Vārttikabharaṇya is a commentary on the Ṭupṭīkā.
Prabhākara (8th century CE), the originator of the second school of the Mīmāṁsā
wrote his commentary Bṛhatī on the Śabara Bhāṣya.
Śālikanātha’s Ṛjuvimalā (9th century CE) is a commentary
on the Bṛhatī.
His Prakaraṇapañcikā is an independent work of this
school and the Pariśiṣṭa is a brief explanation of the Śabara
Bhāṣya.
Bhavanātha’s Nyāyaviveka deals with the views of this school in details. The
founder of the third school of the Mīmāṁsā was Murāri, whose works have not
reached us.
Āpadeva
(17th century) wrote an elementary work on the Mīmāṁsā,
known as Mīmāṁsānyāyaprakaśa or Āpadevī. Arthasaṁgraha
of Laugākṣi Bhāskara is based on the Āpadevī.
Vedānta Deśika’s Śeśvara Mīmāṁsā was an attempt to combine the views
of the Mīmāṁsā and the Vedānta schools.
Epistemology
In
the field of epistemology, later Mimamsakas made some notable contributions.
Unlike the Nyaya or the Vaisheshika systems, the Prābhākara school recognizes
five pramanas (means of valid knowledge) and the Bhāṭṭa
school recognizes six. In addition to the four pramanas (pratyakṣa,
anumāna, upamāna and śabda) accepted by the Nyaya school, the Prābhākara school
recognizes arthāpatti (presumption) and the Bhāṭṭa
school recognizes both arthāpatti and anuapalabdhi (non-apprehension) as the
valid means of knowledge. A more interesting feature of the Mimamsa school of
philosophy is its unique epistemological theory of the intrinsic validity of
all cognition as such. It is held that all knowledge is ipso facto true
(Satahprāmāṇyavāda). Thus, what is to be proven is
not the truth of a cognition, but its falsity. The Mimamsakas advocate the
self-validity of knowledge both in respect of its origin (utpatti) and
ascertainment (jñapti). Not only did the Mimamsakas make the very great use of
this theory to establish the unchallengeable validity of the Vedas, but later
Vedantists also drew freely upon this particular Mimamsa contribution.
Dharma and atheism
Dharma
as understood by Poorva Mimāmsā can be loosely translated into English as
"virtue", "morality" or "duty". The Poorva
Mimāmsā school traces the source of the knowledge of dharma neither to
sense-experience nor inference, but to verbal cognition (i.e. knowledge of
words and meanings) according to Vedas. In this respect it is related to the
Nyaya school, the latter, however, allows less Prāmānas (proofs) than Poorva
Mimāmsā.
The
Poorva Mimāmsā school held dharma to be equivalent to following the
prescriptions of the Samhitas and their Brahmana commentaries relating the
correct performance of Vedic rituals. Seen in this light, Poorva Mimamsa is
essentially ritualist (orthopraxy), placing great weight on the performance of
Karma or action as enjoined by the Vedas.
Emphasis
of Yajnic Karmakāndas in Poorva Mimāmsā is erroneously interpreted by some to
be an opposition to Jnānakānda of Vedānta and Upanishadas. Poorva Mimāmsā does
not discuss topics related to Jnānakānda, such as moksha or salvation, but it
never speaks against moksha. Vedānta quotes Jaimini's belief in Brahman as well
as in moksha:
In
Uttara-Mīmāmsā or Vedānta (4.4.5-7), Bādarāyana cites Jaimini as saying (ब्राह्मेण जैमिनिरूपन्यासादिभ्यः) "(The mukta Purusha is united
with the Brahman) as if it were like the Brahman, because descriptions (in
Shruti etc) prove so".
In
Vedānta (1.2.28), Bādarāyana cites Jaimini as saying that "There is no
contradictiction in taking Vaishvānara as the supreme Brahman".
In
1.2.31, Jaimini is again quoted by Bādarāyana as saying that the nirguna
Brahman can manifest itself as having a form.
In
4.3.12, Bādarāyana again cites Jaimini as saying that the mukta Purusha attains
Brahman.
In
Poorva Mimāmsā too, Jaimini emphasises the importance of faith in and
attachment to the Omnipotent Supreme Being Whom Jaimini calls "The
Omnipotent Pradhaana" (The Main):
Poorva
Mimāmsā 6.3.1: "sarvaśaktau pravṛttiḥ syāt tathābhūtopadeśāt" (सर्वशक्तौ प्रवृत्तिः स्यात् तथाभूतोपदेशात्). The term Upadesha here is means
instructions of the Shāstras as taught. We should tend towards the
Omnipotent Supreme Being. In the context of Poorva Mimāmsā 6.3.1 shown above,
next two sutras becomes significant, in which this Omnipotent Being is termed
as "Pradhāna", and keeping away from Him is said to be a "Dosha",
hence all beings are asked to get related ("abhisambandhāt" in
tadakarmaṇi ca doṣas
tasmāt tato viśeṣaḥ syāt pradhānenābhisambandhāt;
Jaimini 6, 3.3) to the "Omnipotent Main Being" (api vāpy ekadeśe syāt
pradhāne hy arthanirvṛttir guṇamātram
itarat tadarthatvāt; Jaimini 6, 3.2). Karma-Mīmāmsā supports the Vedas, and
Rgveda says that one Truth is variously named by the sages. It is irrelevant
whether we call Him as Pradhāna or Brahman or Vaishvānara or Shiva or God. With
such explicit ideas in Poorva-Mīmāmsā, and supportive evidences from
Uttara-Mīmāmsā, it is wrong to say that the concept of Supreme God is absent in
Poorva-Mīmāmsā. Poorva-Mīmāmsā believes in Vedas and in Yajnas performed for
gods (Devatās), hence it is wrong to call it atheist, especially in light of
explicit affirmation of its faith in the Omnipotent (Poorva Mimāmsā 6.3.1)
SANKHYA
Sankhya,
also Sankhya, Sāṃkhya, or Sāṅkhya
(Sanskrit: सांख्य, IAST: sāṃkhya - 'enumeration') is one of the six
schools of classical Indian philosophy. Sage Kapila is traditionally considered
as the founder of the Sankhya school, although no historical verification is
possible. It is regarded as one of the oldest philosophical systems in India.
Sankhya
was one of the six orthodox systems (astika, those systems that recognize vedic
authority) of Hindu philosophy. The major text of this Vedic school is the
extant Sankhya Karika, circa 200 CE. This text (in karika 70) identifies
Sankhya as a Tantra and its philosophy was one of the main influences both on
the rise of the Tantras as a body of literature, as well as Tantra sadhana[3].
There are no purely Sankhya schools existing today in Hinduism, but its
influence is felt in the Yoga and Vedanta schools.
Sankhya
is an enumerationist philosophy that is strongly dualist. Sankhya philosophy
regards the universe as consisting of two realities: Purusha (consciousness)
and Prakriti (phenomenal realm of matter). They are the experiencer and the
experienced, not unlike the res cogitans and res extensa of René Descartes.
Prakriti further bifurcates into animate and inanimate realms. On the other
hand, Purusha separates out into countless Jivas or individual units of
consciousness as souls which fuse into the mind and body of the animate branch
of Prakriti.
There
are differences between Sankhya and Western forms of dualism. In the West, the
fundamental distinction is between mind and body. In Sankhya, however, it is
between the self (as Purusha) and matter (Prakriti).
Literature
Sage
Kapila is considered as the founder of the Sankhya school, but there is no
evidence to prove that the texts attributed to him, the Sāṁkhyapravacana
Sūtra and the Tattvasamāsa were actually composed by him. According to a modern
scholar Surendranath Dasgupta, the doctrine of the earliest school of Sankhya
is found in an ancient Indian medical treatise, Charaka Samhita . Another early
extant text of this school is Sāṁkhya Kārikā of Iśvarakṛṣṇa
(3rd century). Iśvarakṛṣṇa in his Kārikā described himself as
being in the succession of the disciples from Kapila, through Āsuri and
Pañcaśikha. Gauḍapāda wrote a commentary on this
Kārikā. The next important work is Vācaspati’s Sāṁkhyatattvakaumudī
(9th century AD). Nārāyaṇa’s treatise Sāṁkhyacandrikā
is based on the Kārikā. The Sāṁkhyapravacana Sūtra is assigned to the
14th century, as Guṇaratna (14th century) did not refer to
this text but referred to the Kārikā. This text consists of 6 chapters and 526
sūtras. The most important commentary on the Sāṁkhyapravacana
Sūtra is Vijñānabhikṣu’s Sāṁkhyapravacanabhāṣya
(16th century).
Anirruddha’s
Kāpilasāṁkhyapravacanasūtravṛtti
(15th century) and Mahādeva’s Sāṁkhyapravacanasūtravṛttisāra
(c. 1600) and Nāgeśa’s Laghusāṁkhyasūtravṛtti
are the other important commentaries on this text.
Epistemology
According
to the Sankhya school, all knowledge is possible through three pramanas (means
of valid knowledge) -
1.
Pratyaksha or Drishtam - direct sense perception,
2.
Anumana - logical inference and
3. Sabda
or Aptavacana - verbal testimony.
Sankhya cites two kinds of perceptions:
Indeterminate
(nirvikalpa) perceptions and determinate (savikalpa) perceptions.
Indeterminate
perceptions are merely impressions without understanding or knowledge. They
reveal no knowledge of the form or the name of the object. There is only
external awareness about an object. There is cognition of the object, but no
discriminative recognition.
For
example, a baby’s initial experience is full of impression. There is a lot of
data from sensory perception, but there is little or no understanding of the
inputs. Hence they can be neither differentiated nor labeled. Most of them are
indeterminate perceptions.
Determinate
perceptions are the mature state of perceptions which have been processed and
differentiated appropriately. Once the sensations have been processed,
categorized, and interpreted properly, they become determinate perceptions.
They can lead to identification and also generate knowledge.
Metaphysics
Ontology
Broadly, the Sankhya system classifies
all objects as falling into one of the two categories: Purusha and Prakriti.
Metaphysically, Sankhya maintains an intermingled duality between
spirit/consciousness (Purusha) and matter (Prakrti).
Purusha
Purusha
is the Transcendental Self or Pure Consciousness. It is absolute, independent,
free, imperceptible, unknowable, above any experience and beyond any words or
explanation. It remains pure, “nonattributive consciousness ”. Purusha is
neither produced nor does it produce. Unlike Advaita Vedanta and like
Purva-Mimamsa, Sankhya believes in plurality of the Purushas.
Prakriti
Prakriti
is the first cause of the universe—of everything except the Purusha, which is
uncaused, and accounts for whatever is physical, both matter and force. Since
it is the first principle (tattva) of the universe, it is called the Pradhana,
but, as it is the unconscious and unintelligent principle, it is also called
the Jada. It is composed of three essential characteristics (trigunas). These
are:
*
sattva - fineness, lightness, illumination, and joy;
*
rajas - activity, excitation, and pain;
*
tamas - coarseness, heavyness, obstruction, and sloth.
All
physical events are considered to be manifestations of the evolution of
Prakriti, or primal nature (from which all physical bodies are derived). Each
sentient being is a Purusha, and is limitless and unrestricted by its physical
body. Samsaara or bondage arises when the Purusha does not have the
discriminate knowledge and so is misled as to its own identity, confusing
itself with the physical body, which is actually an evolute of Prakriti. The
spirit is liberated when the discriminate knowledge of the difference between
conscious Purusha and unconscious Prakriti is realized.
Ishvara (Creationist God)
The
Sānkhyapravacana Sūtra states that there is no philosophical place for a
creationist God in this system. It is also argued in this text that the existence
of Ishvara cannot be proved and hence cannot be admitted to exist and an
unchanging Ishvara as the cause cannot be the source of a changing world as the
effect. Almost all modern scholars are of view that the concept of Ishvara was
incorporated into the nirishvara (atheistic) Sankhya viewpoint only after it
became associated with the Yoga, the Pasupata and the Bhagavata schools of
philosophy. This theistic Sankhya philosophy is described in the Mahabharata,
the Puranas and the Bhagavad Gita.
Nature
of Duality
The
Sankhya recognizes only two ultimate entities, Prakriti and Purusha. While the
Prakriti is a single entity, the Sankhya admits a plurality of the Purushas.
Unintelligent, unmanifest, uncaused, ever-active, imperceptible and eternal
Prakriti is alone the final source of the world of objects which is implicitly
and potentially contained in its bosom. The Purusha is considered as the
intelligent principle, a passive enjoyer (bhokta) and the Prakriti is the
enjoyed (bhogya). Sankhya believes that the Purusha cannot be regarded as the
source of inanimate world, because an intelligent principle cannot transform
itself into the unintelligent world. It is a pluralistic spiritualism,
atheistic realism and uncompromising dualism.
Consciousness/Matter-dualism.
Theory of Existence
The
Sankhya system is based on Satkaryavada. According to Satkaryavada, the effect
pre-exists in the cause. Cause and effect are seen as different temporal
aspects of the same thing - the effect lies latent in the cause which in turn seeds
the next effect.
More specifically, Sankhya system follows the Prakriti-Parinama Vada. Parinama
denotes that the effect is a real transformation of the cause. The cause under
consideration here is Prakriti or more precisely Mula-Prakriti (Primordial Matter).
The Sankhya system is therefore an exponent of an evolutionary theory of matter
beginning with primordial matter. In evolution, Prakriti is transformed and
differentiated into multiplicity of objects. Evolution is followed by
dissolution. In dissolution the physical existence, all the worldly objects
mingle back into Prakriti, which now remains as the undifferentiated,
primordial substance. This is how the cycles of evolution and dissolution
follow each other.
The twenty-four principles
Sankhya
theorizes that Prakriti is the source of the world of becoming. It is pure
potentiality that evolves itself successively into twenty four tattvas or
principles. The evolution itself is possible because Prakriti is always in a
state of tension among its constituent strands -
*
Sattva - a template of balance or equilibrium;
*
Rajas - a template of expansion or activity;
*
Tamas - a template of inertia or resistance to action.
All
macrocosmic and microcosmic creation uses these templates. The twenty four principles
that evolve are -
*
Prakriti - The most subtle potentiality that is behind whatever is created in
the physical universe, also called "primordial Matter". It is also a
state of equilibrium amongst the Three Gunas.
*
Mahat - first product of evolution from Prakriti, pure potentiality. Mahat is
also considered to be the principle responsible for the rise of buddhi or
intelligence in living beings.
* Ahamkara or ego-sense - second product of evolution. It is responsible for
the self-sense in living beings. It is also one's identification with the outer
world and its content.
* "Panch Tanmatras" are a simultaneous product from Mahat Tattva,
along with the Ahamkara. They are the subtle form of Panch Mahabhutas which
result from grossification or Panchikaran of the Tanmatras. Each of these
Tanmatras are made of all three Gunas.
*
Manas or "Antahkaran" evolves from the total sum of the sattva aspect
of Panch Tanmatras or the "Ahamkara"
*
Panch jnana indriyas or five sense organs - also evolves from the sattva aspect
of Ahamkara.
* Pancha karma indriya or five organs of action - The organs of action are
hands, legs, vocal apparatus, urino-genital organ and anus. They evolve from
the rajas aspect of Ahamkara.
* Pancha mahabhuta or five great substances - ether, air, fire, water and
earth. They evolve from the "tamas" aspect of the
"Ahamkara". This is the revealed aspect of the physical
universe.
The
evolution of primal nature is also considered to be purposeful - Prakrti
evolves for the spirit in bondage. The spirit who is always free is only a
witness to the evolution, even though due to the absence of discriminate
knowledge, he misidentifies himself with Purusha (body).
The
evolution obeys causality relationships, with primal Nature itself being the
material cause of all physical creation. The cause and effect theory of Sankhya
is called Satkaarya-vaada (theory of existent causes), and holds that nothing
can really be created from or destroyed into nothingness - all evolution is
simply the transformation of primal Nature from one form to another.
The
evolution of matter occurs when the relative strengths of the attributes
change. The evolution ceases when the spirit realizes that it is distinct from
primal Nature and thus cannot evolve. This destroys the purpose of evolution,
thus stopping Prakrti from evolving for Purusha.
Sankhyan
cosmology describes how life emerges in the universe; the relationship between
Purusha and Prakriti is crucial to Patanjali's yoga system. The evolution of
forms at the basis of Sankhya is quite remarkable. The strands of Sankhyan
thought can be traced back to the Vedic speculation of creation. It is also
frequently mentioned in the Mahabharata and Yogavasishta.
Moksha
Like
other major systems of Indian philosophy, Sankhya regards ignorance as the root
cause of bondage and suffering (Samsara). According to Sankhya, the Purusha is
eternal, pure consciousness. Due to ignorance, it identifies itself with the
physical body and its constituents - Manas, Ahamkara and Mahat, which are products
of Prakriti. Once it becomes free of this false identification and the material
bonds, Moksha ensues. Other forms of Sankhya teach that Moksha is attained by
one's own development of the higher faculties of discrimination achieved by
meditation and other yogic practices as prescribed through the Hindu Vedas.
Views
of what happens to the soul after liberation vary tremendously, as the Sankhya
view is used by many different Hindu sects and is rarely practiced alone.
VEDANTA
As
per the teachings contained in the 108+ upanishads
What
is ‘life’? What is its main aim? Who am ‘I’? What is the entity that is to be
understood by the concept that is denoted by the word ‘I’? These are some
questions that have been perturbing the minds of intellectuals and thinkers
from time immemorial. Ancient Indian philosophers conducted specialized studies
to find infallible and precise answers to these questions by means of both
internal and external enquiry. This enquiry was based not on their own
intellect, but on the words of the ancient seers who had intuitional knowledge
that was revealed to them by the grace of none other than the Supreme Lord
Himself.
These
words, which constitute a wide and deep body of divine knowledge, are known as
the ‘Vedas’. The Vedas represent such a vast body of literature that it is very
difficult to understand its purport in a simple manner.
Therefore
the Upanishads emerged, to convey the purport of the Vedas relatively easy and
comprehensible. The word “Vedanta” literally means "end (or culmination)
of the Vedas". The three most important sources for Vedanta are-
Upanishads
(commentaries on the Vedas), the
Bramha Sutras and Bhagavad
Gita.
The
original philosophical text of the Vedanta, the Brahma Sutras of Badarayana, is
purportedly a condensation and systematisation of Upanishadic wisdom, so
concise and abbreviated that it is considered completely incomprehensible. This
ambiguity allowed a huge number of schools and sub schools to develop, each one
based on commentaries on the Upanishads, Brahma sutras, Gita, and other authoritative
texts.
Different
interpretations of the fundamental texts of Vedanta have given rise to three
main schools: Advaita (monistic or nondual) of Adi Shankaracharya,
Visishtadvaita (qualified non- dualism) of Ramanuja and Dvaita (dualism) of
Madhva. There are in addition a variety of other less influential schools like
the Vallabha School, Nimbarka school, Bhaskara school and so on, but these are
the three most important.
Vedanta
generally deals with four topics:
Brahman
(the Supreme or Universal soul)
Jivatman
(the individual soul)
The
Creation of the world
Moksha
(liberation), the final goal of human life
But
these are explained quite differently according to the metaphysical slant of
each particular school.
As
mentioned earlier, Vedanta covers a tremendously wide range of metaphysical
positions; the three most important being the Non-dual Monism or Advaita
Vedanta of Shankara (traditionally 8th-9th century); the Qualified (or
modified) Non-Dualism or Vishishtadvaita Vedanta of Ramanuja
(11th-12th century), and the Dualism or Dvaita Vedanta of Mahdva (13th
century).
As
the titles indicate, only the first is an absolute or true monism, seeing
reality as totally unitary, and identifying all things with the Absolute
(Brahman). The second teaches a multiplicity or plurality within unity, in that
souls and matter are considered "the body" of God (Brahman), but not
identical with his essence; and the third teaches that the Supreme God
(Bhagavan) is totally separate from souls and from the cosmos.
YOGA
The
Yoga Sutras of Patanjali is a foundational text of Yoga. It forms part of the
corpus of Sutra literature.
In
Indian philosophy, Yoga (also Raja Yoga to distinguish it from later schools)
is the name of one of the six orthodox philosophical schools. Though brief, the
Yoga Sutras are an enormously influential work on yoga philosophy and practice,
held by principal proponents of yoga.
Patañjali
fills each sutra with his experiential intelligence, stretching it like a
thread (sūtra), and weaving it into a garland of pearls of wisdom to flavor and
savor by those who love and live in yoga.
Philosophical
roots and influences
The
Sutras are built on a foundation of Sankhya philosophy and also exhibit the
influence of Upanishadic, Buddhist and Jain thought. Karel Werner writes that
"Patanjali's system is unthinkable without Buddhism. As far as its
terminology goes there is much in the Yoga Sutras that reminds us of Buddhist
formulations from the Pāli Canon and even more so from the Sarvāstivāda
Abhidharma and from Sautrāntika."
Robert
Thurman writes that Patanjali was influenced by the success of the Buddhist
monastic system to formulate his own matrix for the version of thought he
considered orthodox. The five yamas or the constraints of the Yoga Sutras of
Patanjali bear an uncanny resemblance to the five major vows of Jainism,
indicating influence of Jainism. This mutual influence between the Yoga
philosophy and Jainism is admitted by the author
Vivian
Worthington who writes: "Yoga fully acknowledges its debt to Jainism, and
Jainism reciprocates by making the practice of yoga part and parcel of
life."
Christopher
Chappel also notes that three teachings closely associated with Jainism appear
in Yoga: the doctrine of karma described as colourful in both traditions; the
telos of isolation (kevala in Jainism and Kaivalyam in Yoga); and the practice
of non-violence (ahimsa). He also notes that the entire list of five yamas
(II:30) is identical with the ethical precepts (Mahavratas) taught by
Mahavira.
In
the Yoga Sutras, Patanjali prescribes adherence to eight "limbs" or
steps (the sum of which constitute "Ashtanga Yoga", the title of the
second chapter) to quiet one's mind and achieve kaivalya. The Yoga Sutras form
the theoretical and philosophical basis of Raja Yoga, and are considered to be
the most organized and complete definition of that discipline. The division
into the Eight Limbs (Sanskrit Ashtanga) of Yoga is reminiscent of Buddha's
Noble Eightfold Path; inclusion of Brahmaviharas (Yoga Sutra 1:33) also shows
Buddhism's influence on parts of the Sutras.
The
Sutras not only provide yoga with a thorough and consistent philosophical
basis, they also clarify many important esoteric concepts which are common to
all traditions of Indian thought, such as karma.
Usage
Although
Patanjali's work does not cover the many types of Yogic practices that have
become prevalent, its succinct form and availability caused it to be pressed
into service by a variety of schools of Yogic thought.
The
Sutras, with commentaries, have been published by a number of successful
teachers of Yoga, as well as by academicians seeking to clarify issues of
textual variation. There are also other versions from a variety of sources
available on the Internet. The many versions display a wide variation,
particularly in translation. The text has not been submitted in its entirety to
any rigorous textual analysis, and the contextual meaning of many of the
Sanskrit words and phrases remains a matter of some dispute.
Text
Patanjali
divided his Yoga Sutras into 4 chapters or books (Sanskrit pada), containing in
all 196 aphorisms, divided as follows:
*
Samadhi Pada (51 sutras)
Samadhi
refers to a blissful state where the yogi is absorbed into the One. The author
describes yoga and then the nature and the means to attaining samādhi. This
chapter contains the famous definitional verse: "Yogaś
citta-vritti-nirodhaḥ" ("Yoga is the restraint of
mental modifications").
*
Sadhana Pada (55 sutras)
Sadhana
is the Sanskrit word for "practice" or "discipline". Here
the author outlines two forms of Yoga: Kriya Yoga (Action Yoga) and Ashtanga
Yoga (Eightfold or Eightlimbed Yoga).
Kriya
yoga, sometimes called Karma Yoga, is also expounded in Chapter 3 of the
Bhagavad Gita, where Arjuna is encouraged by Krishna to act without attachment
to the results or fruit of action and activity. It is the yoga of selfless
action and service.
Ashtanga
Yoga describes the eight limbs that together constitute Raja Yoga.
*
Vibhuti Pada (56 sutras)
Vibhuti
is the Sanskrit word for "power" or "manifestation".
'Supra-normal powers' (Sanskrit: siddhi) are acquired by the practice of yoga.
The temptation of these powers should be avoided and the attention should be
fixed only on liberation.
*
Kaivalya Pada (34 sutras)
Kaivalya
literally means "isolation", but as used in the Sutras stands for
emancipation, liberation and used interchangeably with moksha (liberation),
which is the goal of Yoga. The Kaivalya Pada describes the nature of liberation
and the reality of the transcendental self.
The
eight limbs (ashtanga) of Raja Yoga
The
eight "limbs" or steps prescribed in the second pada of the Yoga
Sutras are: Yama, Niyama, Asana, Pranayama, Pratyahara, Dharana, Dhyana and
Samadhi.
Ashtanga
yoga consists of the following steps: The first five are called external aids
to Yoga (bahiranga sadhana)
* Yama: refers to the five abstentions.
These are the same as the five vows of Jainism.
* Ahimsa: non-violence, inflicting no
injury or harm to others or even to one's ownself, it goes as far as
nonviolence in thought, word and deed.
* Satya: truth in word & thought.
* Asteya: non-covetousness, to the extent
that one should not even desire something that is not his own.
* Brahmacharya: abstain from sexual intercourse;
celibacy in case of unmarried people and monogamy in case of married people.
Even this to the extent that one should not possess any sexual thoughts towards
any other man or woman except one's own spouse. It's common to associate
Brahmacharya with celibacy.
* Aparigraha: non-possessiveness
* Niyama refers to the five observances
* Shaucha: cleanliness of body & mind.
* Santosha: satisfaction; satisfied with what
one has.
* Tapas: austerity and associated
observances for body discipline & thereby mental control.
* Svadhyaya: study of the Vedic scriptures to
know about God and the soul, which leads to introspection on a greater
awakening to the soul and God within,
* Ishvarapranidhana: surrender to (or worship of) God.
* Asana: Discipline of the body: rules and
postures to keep it disease-free and for preserving vital energy. Correct
postures are a physical aid to meditation, for they control the limbs and
nervous system and prevent them from producing disturbances.
* Pranayama: control of breath. Beneficial to
health, steadies the body and is highly conducive to the concentration of the
mind.
* Pratyahara: withdrawal of senses from their
external objects.
The
last three levels are called internal aids to Yoga (antaranga sadhana)
* Dharana: concentration of the citta upon a
physical object, such as a flame of a lamp, the mid point of the eyebrows, or
the image of a deity.
*
Dhyana: steadfast
meditation. Undisturbed flow of thought around the object of meditation
(pratyayaikatanata). The act of meditation and the object of meditation remain
distinct and separate.
* Samadhi: oneness with the object of
meditation. There is no distinction between act of meditation and the object of
meditation. Samadhi is of two kinds:
o
Samprajnata Samadhi conscious samadhi.
The mind remains concentrated (ekagra) on the object of meditation, therefore
the consciousness of the object of meditation persists. Mental modifications
arise only in respect of this object of meditation.
This
state is of four kinds:
+ Savitarka: the Citta is concentrated upon a
gross object of meditation such as a flame of a lamp, the tip of the nose, or
the image of a deity.
+ Savichara: the Citta is concentrated upon a
subtle object of meditation , such as the tanmatras
+ Sananda: the Citta is concentrated upon a
still subtler object of meditation, like the senses.
+ Sasmita: the Citta is concentrated upon
the ego-substance with which the self is generally identified.
o Asamprajnata Samadhi
supraconscious. The
citta and the object of meditation are fused together. The consciousness of the
object of meditation is transcended. All mental modifications are checked
(niruddha), although latent impressions may continue.
Combined
simultaneous practice of Dhāraṇā, Dhyāna & Samādhi is referred to
as Samyama and is considered a tool of achieving various perfections, or
Siddhis.
Anumāna (inference) is one of the most important contributions of the Nyaya. It can be of two types: inference for oneself (Svarthanumana, where one does not need any formal procedure, and at the most the last three of their 5 steps), and inference for others (Parathanumana, which requires a systematic methodology of 5 steps). Inference can also be classified into 3 types: Purvavat (inferring an unperceived effect from a perceived cause), Sheshavat (inferring an unperceived cause from a perceived effect) and Samanyatodrishta (when inference is not based on causation but on uniformity of co-existence). A detailed anaysis of error is also given, explaining when anumana could be false.
Broadly, the Sankhya system classifies all objects as falling into one of the two categories: Purusha and Prakriti. Metaphysically, Sankhya maintains an intermingled duality between spirit/consciousness (Purusha) and matter (Prakrti).
Purusha
More specifically, Sankhya system follows the Prakriti-Parinama Vada. Parinama denotes that the effect is a real transformation of the cause. The cause under consideration here is Prakriti or more precisely Mula-Prakriti (Primordial Matter). The Sankhya system is therefore an exponent of an evolutionary theory of matter beginning with primordial matter. In evolution, Prakriti is transformed and differentiated into multiplicity of objects. Evolution is followed by dissolution. In dissolution the physical existence, all the worldly objects mingle back into Prakriti, which now remains as the undifferentiated, primordial substance. This is how the cycles of evolution and dissolution follow each other.
* Ahamkara or ego-sense - second product of evolution. It is responsible for the self-sense in living beings. It is also one's identification with the outer world and its content.
* "Panch Tanmatras" are a simultaneous product from Mahat Tattva, along with the Ahamkara. They are the subtle form of Panch Mahabhutas which result from grossification or Panchikaran of the Tanmatras. Each of these Tanmatras are made of all three Gunas.
* Pancha karma indriya or five organs of action - The organs of action are hands, legs, vocal apparatus, urino-genital organ and anus. They evolve from the rajas aspect of Ahamkara.
* Pancha mahabhuta or five great substances - ether, air, fire, water and earth. They evolve from the "tamas" aspect of the "Ahamkara". This is the revealed aspect of the physical universe.
* Samadhi: oneness with the object of meditation. There is no distinction between act of meditation and the object of meditation. Samadhi is of two kinds:
+ Savichara: the Citta is concentrated upon a subtle object of meditation , such as the tanmatras
+ Sananda: the Citta is concentrated upon a still subtler object of meditation, like the senses.
No comments:
Post a Comment